Newsgroups: sci.med.psychobiology From: [s--v--c] at [netcom.com] (Sylvia Caras) Subject: Szasz:Cruel Compassion (24K) Date: Tue, 5 Jul 1994 03:02:07 GMT Thomas Szasz. _Cruel Compassion: Psychiatric Control of Society's Unwanted_, Wiley, 1994. Thomas Szasz, MD, Professor of Psychiatry Emeritus at the SUNY Health Science Center in Syracuse, is recognized as the premier critic of psychiatric coercions and excuses and on of the most important social observers of our age. _Cruel Compassion_ is the capstone of Thomas Szasz's critique of psychiatric practices. Reexamining psychiatric interventions from a cultural-historical and political- economic perspective, Szasz demonstrates that the main problem that faces mental health policy makes today is adult dependency. Millions of Americans, diagnosed as mentally ill, are drugged and confined by doctors for noncriminal conduct, go legally unpunished for the crimes thy commit, and are supported by the state--not because they are sick, but because they are unproductive and unwanted. Obsessed with the twin beliefs that misbehavior is a medical disorder and that the duty of the state is to protect adults from themselves, we have replaced criminal-punitive sentences with civil-therapeutic 'programs.' The result is the relentless los of individual liberty, erosion of personal responsibility, and destruction of the security or persons and property--symptoms of the transformation of a Constitutional Republic into a Therapeutic State, unconstrained by the law. Szasz shows convincingly that not until we separate therapy from coercion--much as the founders separated theology from coercion--shall we be able to get a handle on our seemingly intractable psychiatric and social problems. (From the jacket) Excerpts follow in the order of the book. (W)e should reject infantilizing mental patients and the coercive psychiatric paternalism that hoes with it, and accord the same rights to, and impose the same responsibilities on, these patients as we accord to and impose on patients with bodily illness or with no illness. p xiii Classifying a person as a mental patient is an especially treacherous enterprise, encouraging abstract compassion toward him as a patient, and concrete indifference toward him as a person." p 5 (St Augustine began the Christian policy of coercion for the perfection of the person. This laid a moral foundation for secular force as therapy. Heresy evolved into insanity as is as little tolerated. Charity combined with coercion guarantee adult dependency. The classical sins are now symptoms. The former agent, misusing his free will, behaving wrongly, is now mentally ill.) The ethics of psychiatric therapy is the very negation of the ethics of political liberty. The former embraces absolute power, provided it is used to protect and promote the patient's mental health. The latter rejects absolute power, regardless of its aim or use. By definition, the powers of constitutional government are limited. Hence, there is no room, in such a political framework, for psychiatric power over mental patients that, by definition, is unlimited. ... The whole history of psychiatry then, may be said to come down to the history of the repudiation of limited therapeutic powers. ... (E)very so-called psychiatric advance has consisted of a shameless celebration of the psychiatrist's unlimited power over his patient. p 6 The promise of curing sick people against their will-- especially people whose illnesses we don not understand or who may, in fact, not even be ill--is fraught with perils we seem determined to deny. Despite the ghastly mayhem wrought by psychiatrists in Nazi Germany and The Soviet Union, we continue to venerate the coercive-compassionate psychiatrist. Indeed, there is no popular interest in, or professional support for, a psychiatry stripped of political power. On the contrary, improving the Other by coercion in the name of mental health has become a characteristic feature of our age. p 6 Why do I want to help him? What do I want to help him be or do? p 7 In the United States today, the most unwanted are drug abusers, chronic mental patients,and the homeless. Every politician and psychiatrist now proclaims his determination to help these persons, by enlisting the coercive apparatus of the state in a therapeutic crusade against the sickness that supposedly causes their being unwanted. What the politicians and psychiatrists actually mean is that it is their duty to lead, and the taxpayers' to fund, prohibitively expensive campaigns to save the victims, viewed as defective objects, devoid of both rights and responsibilities. p 7 On p 8, Szasz quotes C. S. Lewis: Of all the tyrannies a tyranny sincerely exercised for the good of its victims may be the most oppressive. ... To be "cured" against one's will and cured of states which we may not regard as disease is to be put on a level with those who have not yet reached the age of reason or those who never will; to be classed with infants, imbeciles, and domestic animals. ... For if crime and disease are to be regarded as the same thing, it follows that any state of mind which our masters choose to call :disease: can be treated as a crime; and compulsorily cured. ... Even if the treatment is painful, even if it is life-long, even if it is fatal, that will be only a regrettable accident; the intention was purely therapeutic. I shall address the (familiar subject of mental hospitalization) as a problem of adult dependency and unwantedness, that is, as a problem of the political- economic and power relations between producers and nonproducers, stigmatizers and stigmatized, intrinsic to modern society. p 9 (W)e need not decide whether mental patients suffer from brain diseases; or if they do, whether such diseases account for their unproductiveness and lawlessness. p 9 (O)ur mental health policies will rest on the principle that adults have rights and responsibilities that are unaffected, much less annulled, by psychiatric diagnoses. In practice, that would mean treating the psychiatrically diagnosed person as a moral agent who is expected to cope with his problems and obey the law. If he asks for help, we offer to help him on terms agreeable to both him and us. If he does not, we leave him alone. And if he breaks the law, we treat him as we would want to be treated by a policeman who stopped us for a traffic violation. p 10 I view our statist-institutional psychiatric practices not as specialized medical technics for treating mental diseases, but as socially approved procedures for disposing of unwanted persons, similar to such past social practices a segregating paupers in workhouses, incarcerating defaulting debtors in prisons, and exiling epileptics to colonies. p 11 (C)ruelty is intrinsic to the mental hospital and accounts for the futility of mental health reforms. p 20 The cruelty intrinsic to the workhouse system was excused by the need to discourage idleness, much as the malice intrinsic to the mental hospital system has been excused by the need to provide treatment. p 22 Not so long ago, people thought they could distinguish between the "beggar," the "sturdy beggar," the "industrious poor," the "laboring poor," the "pauper," the "indigent," and the "impotent." Their strategic fictions, whose aim was to regulate poor relief, were no more or less ridiculous than are our strategic fictions for regulating psychiatric relief, which include categories such as "pathological gambling," "pyromania," factitious disorder," and "insomnia." p 24 ... our present practice of imprisonment for failing to respect personal and social obligation (mental illness). p 27 Nearly everyone realizes that psychiatric coercion does not cure the mental patient and aggravates his conflicts with his relatives, but it punishes the patient (by means of so- called treatments) and discourages people from taking advantage of the largess of the state (free room and board in return for being "psychotic"). Similarly, once commitment laws are enacted, they become an engine of oppression; other laws are then enacted to prevent this from happening, such as laws guaranteeing the patient's right to treatment, to refuse treatment, to a lawyer, to a hearing,and so on; and the more laws, the less protection for the patient, and the more power for his oppressors. p 38 The mental patient: Is (typically accused by a parent or spouse--a person with close and important emotional and economic ties to him--of defaulting on his personal obligation to him (being mentally ill). Is brought to the mental hospital (or some intermediate place of detention) by his relative (or an agent of the state he has summoned). Is involuntarily hospitalized--because that is what his relative wants (the concerned kin has the option of taking the patient into his home or leaving him to his won devices). Ergo, the mental patient forfeits his liberty to his kin (or to a psychiatrist who is his kin's agent). p 41 With respect to the mental patient, the role of the state goes far beyond enforcing laws. Prosecutors and judges regularly instigate and initiate commitment proceedings, especially if the patient is indigent and deemed to be dangerous to himself or others. At the same time, the state plays, or pretends to play, the role of umpire as well, courts being entrusted with the duty of protecting the citizen from abuses of the mental health laws. This dual role of the state makes the practice of civil commitment especially corrupt, farcical, and tragic. p 42 (P)sychiatrists now treat some mental patients with convulsions, others with anticonvulsant drugs, maintain that both are cures for mental diseases--and most people believe them. p 56 The differences between the neurological and psychiatric attitudes toward patients could hardly be more dramatic. The neurologist eschews dominating, much less coercing, patients suffering from _demonstrable_ brain diseases. The psychiatrist, protesting more stridently than ever that mental patients suffer from brain diseases, clings to his power to impose unwanted interventions on nonconsenting nonpatients. p 59 Unlike Nazi psychiatrists, democratic psychiatrists do not literally kill their patients. They kill them metaphorically, by incarcerating, shocking, and drugging them. p 60 (P)eople find it intolerable to witness a person talking to himself, depressed, contemplating suicide. The public want to be spared this spectacle. To accommodate this desire, psychiatrists declare that (seriously ill) mental patients need to be confined in institutions. That is not the official version of the story. It is considered unprofessional to acknowledge that doctors dispose of unwanted persons at the behest of society. p 61 If the psychiatrist has no effective remedies for mental illness, then he cannot appeal to treatment as a justification for depriving the patient of liberty. And if the psychiatrist does possess effective treatments for mental illness, then ... the patient's alleged need for treatment ceases to be a legitimate reason for depriving him of liberty. p 62 Anyone familiar with the mental health industry knows that suicide is now the single most effective tool for promoting, justifying, and selling psychiatry. The threat of suicide, fear of suicide, gesture of committing suicide, attribution of wanting to commit suicide, promise of preventing suicide, claim of having successfully prevented suicide, each of these fears, threats, and promises stokes the furnaces of the madhouse industry, especially of its children's division. p 80 The United States loves to dispose of its unwanted children by means of psychiatric storage ... . ... the countless catastrophic consequences of child psychiatry, such as the wholesale psychopathologizing of child misbehavior and the mass poisoning of "hyperactive" children with Ritalin and other neuroleptic drugs. p 84 Unlike the regular doctor, the early psychiatrist, called mad-doctor, treated persons who did not want to be his patients, and whose ailments manifested themselves by exciting the resentment of their relatives. ... Unconventional behavior must have existed for as long as human beings have lived together in society. Psychiatry begins when people stop interpreting such behavior in religious and existential terms, and begin to interpret it in medical terms. The fatal weakness of most psychiatric historiographies lies in the historians' failure to give sufficient weight to the role of coercion in psychiatry and to acknowledge that mad-doctoring had nothing to do with healing. p 104 Stripped of three hundred years of psychiatric-semantic embellishments, the fact is that a mad person appears to his relatives as an unpleasant individual whose company they would rather avoid. to deny their embarrassing lack of love for their lunatic kin, people burdened by a crazy relative now call him their "loved one," especially when they enlist a psychiatrist to dispose of him. p 104 Both the medicalization of madness and the infantilization of the insane were, and are, needed to reconcile a society's devotion to the ideals of individual liberty and responsibility with its desire to relieve itself of certain troublesome individuals my means other than those provided by the criminal law. p 105 (B)etween his teens and his twenties, the young person must learn to become useful to others and stand on his own feet. If he fails to accomplish this task, he and his family are destined to face serious difficulties, nowadays often conceptualized in psychiatric terms, typically as the manifestations of schizophrenia. p 144 (T)he condition (psychiatrists) call schizophrenia refers to a young person's idleness, not is illness. p 146 If this road map to the destination of a schizophrenic career is accurate, then it is clear why psychiatric treatments cannot help such persons. By conceptualizing the young adult's uselessness as an illness, psychiatric interventions can only harm him because they render his chances of becoming useful, self-respecting person even slimmer. p 146 (R)esponsibility for the care of children, old people, and the sick was gradually transferred from the family to the state. Sociologist David Poponoe calls the result a "client society ... in which citizens are for the most part clients of a large group of public employees who take care of them throughout their lives." p 149 The state assumed the dual obligation of protecting itself from the madman and the madman from himself, and authorized the mad-doctor to implement and enforce this principle. Thus did the systematic, forcible incarceration of unwanted persons, qua dangerous mental patients, become the social policy, called "mental hospitalization." p 151 The contrast drawn between the mental hospital and the community is a lie. The domiciles now housing chronic mental patients are neither more nor less a part of the community than the state hospital. p 152 I maintain that neither long-term mental hospitalization nor deinstitutionalization has anything to do with illness, treatment, or medicine. Both are legal and socioeconomic policies, using medical rhetoric as justificatory pretexts. p 152 Today, virtually every mental patient is "on drugs" and the result is that there are now more mental patients than ever, the cost of caring for them is greater than ever, and the patients are more disabled, more destructive, and more dissatisfied with psychiatry than ever. p 161 Although no one in an official position would admit it, deinstitutionalized mental patients became homeless not because they were discharged prematurely, nor because they stopped taking their medication, nor because they are schizophrenics, but because the hospitals were their only homes. E. Fuller Torrey's book on the homeless mentally ill, _Nowhere To Go_, is aptly titled. However, having nowhere to go is a tragedy, not a brain disease. p 164 The insane person could now be controlled with a chemical, instead of a mechanical, straight-jacket: The restraint could be put _in_ him, instead of _on_ him. p 166 Restraint by chemical means does not make (the psychiatrist) feel guilty; herein lies the danger to the patient. p 167 supported by politicians and journalists, psychiatrists managed to convince the public that the care of mental patients had been revolutionized by antipsychotics, much as the care of patients with infectious diseases had been revolutionized by antibiotics. This preposterous claim helped psychiatrists conceal the true nature of the problems mental patients present and the solutions psychiatrists offer to solve them--specifically, that the typical chronic mental patient is homeless and is economically dependent on his family or society; that he violates marginal (or not so marginal) social rules; and that he is restrained, during hospitalization as well as after discharge, by drugs, the threat of commitment, and involuntary mental hospitalization. Today the traditional functions of the madhouse are exercised by many other institutions as well, especially the public facilities of our large cities, such as libraries, bus stations, and so forth. Bedlam is now everywhere, making our streets and parks both ugly and unsafe. Ugly, because we tolerate unacceptable behavior by persons so long as, de jure, they are classified as mental patients; and unsafe, because many of these individuals engage in de facto aggression, depriving others of property, liberty, and even life. p 168 Excerpting and paraphrasing: Nursing homes are really the psychiatric institutions of the 90s, nursing homes where, embalmed in neuroleptic drugs, residents are stored until they can be properly buried. Fearing nursing homes is a major cause of suicide overshadowing depression, chronic illness, and pain. p 171-2 The commingling of crime and disease, which began to infect the body politic in the nineteenth century, has now reached the stage of a far-advanced parasitic infestation of both the criminal justice and mental health systems. The term _deinstitutionalization conceals some simple truths, namely, that old, unwanted persons, formerly housed in state hospitals, are now housed in nursing homes; that young, unwanted persons, formerly also housed in state hospitals, are now housed in prisons or parapsychiatric facilities; and that both groups of inmates are systematically drugged with psychiatric medications. p 174 (T)here is pressure to define ever more types of undesirable behaviors as mental disorders or addictions and to spend ever more tax dollars on developing new psychiatric diagnoses and facilities for storing and treating the victims of such diseases, whose members now include alcoholics, drug abusers, smokers, overeaters, self- starvers, gamblers, etc. p 177 De jure, the psychiatrist functions as a physician diagnosing and treating mental illness; de facto, he is an agent of the state empowered to confine persons in mental hospitals and charge their insurance carriers for the "service." Calling this practice the "delivery of mental health services," and a "market transaction" to boot, is a debauchment of language worthy of Orwell's Newspeak. p 178 The phrase _in the community_ is a psychiatric euphemism intended to conceal the fact that the patient was transferred from one psychiatric facility to another, the first called a "hospital," the second not called a "hospital." p 180 Psychiatrists estimate that from 50 to 90 percent of patients discharged from mental hospitals on drugs exhibit such "noncompliance." Why do they? Is it because they have no insight into their illness and need for medication? Or because they do not like the effects of the drugs and prefer being psychotic? Or because they want to relapse and be readmitted to the hospital? The explanation we choose says more about us than about the patients. p 180 The forcible eviction of desocialized patients from mental hospitals is a moral scandal on par with the forcible involuntary mental hospitalization of persons who are not desocialized. The responsibility for both rest squarely on the shoulders of psychiatrists. p 184 Ever since individuals deemed to be insane were first incarcerated in madhouses, each new method of coercing them- -from replacing chains with commitment laws, or exchanging camisoles for chemicals--has been romanticized as a reform and defined as a "patient liberation." Indeed, one of the most ironic features of psychiatric history is that the greatest oppressors of the mental patient--Philippe Pinel, Eugen Bleuler, Karl Menninger--are officially venerated as their most compassionate champions. In their zeal to diagnose and doctor madness, psychiatrists have tried everything except eschewing coercion and treating the patient as a responsible person. p 187 It is not possible to understand the ugliness of the policy of drugging and deinstitutionalization unless we recognize that, once more in the history of psychiatry, it is something psychiatrists have done to involuntary mental patients. In the past, psychiatrists used their power to imprison individuals in mental hospitals for life. Now they use their power to drug patients for life. p 189 The mental hospital system endures because it fulfills important personal and social needs. It segregates and supports adult dependents--who embarrass, burden, and disturb their families and the community. It incarcerates and incapacitates troublesome lawbreakers--who embarrass, burden, and disturb the judicial and penal systems. And, most importantly, it performs these functions by means of civil law sanctions--in a manner that pleases and pacifies the consciences of politicians, professionals, and the majority of the people. Hence, not only is there no popular interest in abolishing involuntary psychiatric interventions, but, on the contrary, there is intense pressure--especially from the parents of mental patients, the judiciary, and the media--to reinforce the institution of psychiatry. p 200 (I)nvoluntary mental hospitalization is counterproductive, because it deprives the subject of dignity and liberty, excuses him from responsibility for his behavior, and prevents him from learning by suffering the consequences of his selfish or unwise actions. ... p 204 If civil commitment were abolished, mental hospitals as we know them would disappear. Regardless of their psychiatric diagnosis, persons who break the law would have to be accused of a crime, tried, and, if found guilty, punished in the criminal justice system; whereas persons innocent of crime would have to be left unmolested by the legal and psychiatric systems. Only then would mental illness be destigmatized and psychiatrists resemble regular physicians whose practice is limited to treating voluntary patients. p 204 It is dishonest to pretend that caring coercively for the mentally ill invariably helps him, and that abstaining from such coercion is tantamount to "withholding treatment" from him. every social policy entails benefits as well as harms. although our ideas about benefits and harms vary from time to time, all history teaches us to beware of benefactors who deprive their beneficiaries of liberty. p 205 -- ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~ [S--v--C] at [netcom.com] v/f:408 426 5335 Sylvia Caras, 146-5 Chrystal Ter, Santa Cruz CA 95060 It is not up to you to finish the work, but neither are you free to not take it up. %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%